Home » thomas aquinas

2024 Summer: A Thomistic Defense of Democracy

Can democracy be saved? Ours, on both the left and the right, seems to be a world viewed increasingly through post-liberal lenses.  Must we return to a strict hierarchy if we are to abandon the “liberal experiment” that has rendered increasing ailment in recent decades—if, that is, we are not to lapse into socialist totalitarianism?  These are not questions with simple or straightforward answers.  To answer them, we would be foolish both to ignore St. Thomas Aquinas and to caricaturize his thought to fit facile solutions.  Thankfully, though under the auspices of a somewhat different world, great Thomistic thinkers have already anticipated the question and can provide us guidance going forward. Consider these words of Jacques Maritain (1882—1973):

The famous saying of Aristotle that man is a political animal does not mean only that man is naturally made to live in society; it also means that man naturally asks to lead a political life and to participate actively in the life of the political community. It is upon this posulate of human nature that political liberties and political rights rest, and particularly the right of suffrage. Perhaps it is easier for men to renounce active participation in political life; in certain cases it may even have happened that they felt happier and freer from care while dwelling in the commonwealth as political slaves, or while passively handing over to the leaders all the care of the management of the community.  But in this case they gave up a privilege proper to their nature, one of those privileges which, in a sense, makes life more difficult and which brings with it a greater or lesser amount of labor, strain and suffering, but which corresponds to human dignity.

Jacques Maritain, The Rights of Man and Natural Law.

Many are familiar with Jacques Maritain, great Thomist author and figure of the twentieth century: a man who wrote on topics far and wide, and strove most of his life to bring a living Thomism into a broader public.  Fewer are familiar with the thought of Yves Simon, scion of Maritain’s approach to understanding St. Thomas, and an adept thinker and careful author in his own right.

Among Simon’s many contributions is his Philosophy of Democratic Government, a work which presents the core insights of Maritain concerning the nature of democracy in a more deeply-rooted scholarly appraisal of St. Thomas, and rife with many additional insights of Simon’s own.  Using this text as our basis, this seminar, taught by Dr. Francisco Plaza, will revisit these twentieth-century thinkers and discern how their thought can help address the troubles of our own times. Registration closes June 6.

Schedule

Discussion Sessions

11:15pm ET

(World times)
Study Topics &
Readings


Week I
 
06/02–06/08
Lecture 1: Christianity and Democracy
Readings:
» Jacques Maritain, Christianity and Democracy, pages 3 to 63
Week II
 
06/09–06/15
Lecture 2: General Theory of Government
Reading:
» Yves Simon, Philosophy of Democratic Government, pages 1 to 71.
Week III
 
06/16–06/22
Lecture 3: Democratic Freedom
Reading:
» Yves Simon, Philosophy of Democratic Government, pages 72 to 143.
Week IV
 
06/23–06/29
Lecture 4: Sovereignty in Democracy
Reading:
» Yves Simon, Philosophy of Democratic Government, pages 144 to 194.

BREAK
Week V
 
07/07–07/13
Lecture 5: Democratic Equality
Reading:
» Yves Simon, Philosophy of Democratic Government, pages 195 to 259.
Week VI
 
07/14–07/20
Lecture 6: Democracy and Technology
Reading:
» Yves Simon, Philosophy of Democratic Government, pages 260 to 321.
Week VII
 
07/21–07/27
Lecture 7: The Failure of Liberalism
Readings:
» Patrick Deneen, Why Liberalism Failed, pages 1 to 42; pages to 179 to 198.
Week VIII
 
07/28–08/03
Lecture 8: Freedom, Nature, Community, and Democracy
Readings:
» Yves Simon Reader, pages 134 to 148; pages 267 to 284; pages 289 to 298; pages 399 to 414; pages 433 to 446.

Registration

Lyceum Institute seminar costs are structured on a principle of financial subsidiarity. There are three payment levels, priced according to likely levels of income. If you wish to take a seminar but cannot afford the suggested rate, it is acceptable to sign up at a less-expensive level. The idea is: pay what you can. Those who can pay more, should, so that those who cannot pay as much, need not. Lyceum Institute members receive a further discount (see here for details).

One payment covers all 8 weeks.

If you prefer an alternative payment method (i.e., not PayPal), use our contact form and state whether you prefer to pay as a Participant, Patron, or Benefactor, and an invoice will be emailed to you.

Pricing Comparison

Standard priceBasic Lyceum
Enrollment
Advanced Lyceum EnrollmentPremium Lyceum Enrollment
Benefactor$200 per seminar$903 seminars included
$90 after
8 seminars included
$90 after
Patron$135 per seminar$653 seminars included
$65 after
8 seminars included
$65 after
Participant$60 per seminar$403 seminars included
$40 after
8 seminars included
$40 after

On Arguing God’s Existence

A Philosophical Happy Hour on the Unseriousness of Modern Objectors

It has become fashionable for analytic philosophers in recent years[1] to attack arguments for the existence of God.  These attacks, though their permutations are quite numerous, ordinarily attempt to show that the conception of God somehow entails a contradiction.  These might include some form of the problem of evil: namely, that if there is an infinitely good God, how can there be evil—or at least, “gratuitous” evils?  Another popular claim is that God’s omnipotence would contradict our freedom.  Others still might say that arguments for God fail because they presume a premise which is unproven or indemonstrable, against which some alternative can or might be proposed.

But are these objections serious?

To clarify the question, by “serious” I mean: consistently seeking an understanding of the truth in a way befitting our capacities as human beings.

Thus, to answer the question: no, I do not think so.  Why not?

Serious Inquiry

What makes an inquiry serious?  For a difficult and important question—one where belief in the answer not only has significant consequences for our behavior but which lacks an easy resolution—seriousness begins in humility.  To undertake an inquiry with humility requires a recognition of what one does not know and that it might influence the arguments at stake.

For instance, take the average person of today and ask him or her to read St. Thomas Aquinas’ five ways arguing for the existence of God.  Even most skeptics will doubtless admit that, absent prior extensive experience in philosophy and terminological clarifications, the arguments are not likely to be understood very well.  But just what does one have to know in order rightly to interpret Aquinas’ arguments?  Is it merely a matter of reading all of Aquinas’ works (no small feat)?  Of all of Aristotle’s works?  Augustine’s?  Albertus Magnus’?  Do we need the disputations of Scotus, the clarifications of Cajetan, the Iberian schools?  What of 20th century Thomism?

The point here is not that one need to read all of these thinkers to take seriously Aquinas’ arguments—but it is to say that the seriousness of the argument is manifestly indicated by the wide range of thinkers who have engaged with Aquinas’ thought.  These engagements, further—if examined closely in themselves—reveal that interpretation of Aquinas himself seldom proves straightforward.  Time, language, circumstance, and myriad other factors alter one’s interpretive disposition.  Absent careful and thoughtful consideration of these factors, we invariably import meanings into the argument that the argument does not itself contain and thereby turn it into a strawman.

No serious inquiry does this. 

Unserious Arguments

That modern objectors to the existence of God commonly (which is not to say universally) lack the requisite humility and therefore seriousness to undertake a serious inquiry can be seen through some common characteristics of these arguments.  Allow me to draw attention to five of these.

First, it does seem almost universally the case that modern analytic philosophers, to attempt handling such arguments, always translate them not only into anachronistic language (i.e., using modern terms with modern meanings for ancient or scholastic concepts) but further translate these into the artificial languages of symbolic logic.  While symbolic logic proves very useful for grasping the form and validity of arguments, it actively detracts from grasping the soundness and the significance of the terms.

Second, it is common for these arguments to rely upon presuppositions concerning time, matter, and causality, often deflecting responsibility for answering these questions onto idioscopic science or simply ignoring the necessity of their explicit investigation.  These presuppositions, being erroneous, lead naturally to erroneous conclusions.  This becomes doubly-problematic when these erroneous presuppositions are used to interpret arguments from antiquity—torturing their meaning by a Procrustean framework.

Third, many of the arguments against the necessity of a first cause affect their conclusions by subtly shifting claims’ intended significance—a kind of equivocation—to focus on parts rather than wholes.  For instance, in objecting to the first way, Schmid and Linford (2023: Existential Inertia and Classical Theistic Proofs, 22) read “everything” (or “whatever”; in Latin, omne) in Aquinas’ first way to signify “each and every single thing”, when it is said that everything moved is moved by another and that, since this cannot go on to infinity, there must be some first mover.  But had Aquinas intended “each and every single thing”, he would not have used the word omne, but, rather, quodcumque, quilibet, or the like, as he does seemingly everywhere.  Put otherwise, omne is not here used distributively but collectively.[2]

This leads to the fourth point of unseriousness: the objectors seem, by and large, not to themselves ask with intent to answer the questions put forward by defenders of God’s existence, but, rather, only to find possible refutations of them.  Subsequently, their intent seems not to be conviction but rather persuasion, whether or not conviction is a part of that persuasion.  Thus, one will often find a kind of moral outrage—“how dare your God commit such atrocities!”—without any consideration that it could be our understanding which is wrong, and not God.

Fifth and finally, though hard to notice or accurately summarize them, certain noetic presuppositions stand behind and shape the objections.  Because the objectors themselves do not state explicitly their presuppositions (and perhaps are not even consciously aware of them), they make themselves known primarily by a kind of absence.  Nominalism,[3] for example, or an effete empiricism[4] being quite common.  By such presuppositions, and by maintaining them as necessary conditions for any debate, a skeptical objector establishes the impossibility of any argument for God’s existence.

Conversation and Disputation

In describing why thinkers may adopt an absurd conclusion (and specifically in this case, those who deny the principle of non-contradiction), Aquinas writes the following:[5]

Some of these thinkers lapse into this position on account of doubt: for, since certain sophistical rationales occur to them, from which the aforesaid positions seem to follow, and they do not know how to solve these, they concede the conclusions.  Hence their ignorance is easily cured.  For one must not strive to meet or attack the rationales which they posit, but rather make appeal to their minds, so as to resolve the doubts through which their minds have fallen into such opinions.  And thus, from this, they will withdraw from those positions.

Others, however, pursue the aforesaid positions not because some doubt induces them to these opinions, but only for the sake of expression, that is, from a certain impudence, wishing to sustain these impossible arguments on account of their own sakes—because the contraries of these positions cannot be demonstrated.  And the treatment for these thinkers is argumentation or rejection of that which is expressed in speech and in words, that is, from the fact that the expressions of speech signify something.  For the signification of speech depends upon the signification of words.  And thus it is necessary to have recourse to the principle that words signify something.

Thomas Aquinas 1270/71: Super Sententiam Metaphysicae, lib.4, lec.10, n.663-664. Translation my own.

Now… I do not mean to suggest that the objectors here being identified are as sophistical and egotistical as those who would deny the principle of non-contradiction.  Nonetheless, it bears asking: what is it that truly they are expressing in speech and words?  Do they maintain their objections from a certain impudence?  Are they befuddled by sophistical rationalizations?

Join us this Wednesday to think and discuss (not to debate) how one seriously inquires into the existence of God. [Note: this Happy Hour will be recorded, but this recording will be kept strictly within the Lyceum Institute.]

Philosophical Happy Hour

« »

Come join us for drinks (adult or otherwise) and a meaningful conversation. Open to the public! Held every Wednesday from 5:45–7:15pm ET.


[1] I suppose this is true in much of the history of analytic philosophy, but the internet has renewed the trend’s interest and vigor.

[2] Oppy 2023: “Validity and Soundness in the First Way” in Revista Portuguesa de Filosofia, 79.1-2: 148-49 makes precisely the same mistake.  To be fair to Schmid and Linford, they are responding more directly to an interpretation of Aquinas—that by McNabb and DeVito—than to Aquinas himself.  But this in itself is a problem.  Reliance upon interpretations of translations (in this case, by those of Fr. Lawrence Shapcote OP and Anton Pegis), rather than directly addressing the proper signification of the Latin as used by Aquinas, will always be like fighting a shadow with a flashlight.

[3] We can identify both a positive and a negative form of nominalism: positively, as the belief that only individuals exist; negatively, as the denial that mind-independent relations exist or, what is functionally the same, that they can be known by us.

[4] That is, the belief that for a statement to be meaningful there has to be a concrete empirical object which fully instantiates that statement’s meaning.

[5] 1270/71: Super Sententiam Metaphysicae, lib.4, lec.10, n.663-664: “Quidam enim [aliqui incidunt in praedicas positiones] ex dubitatione.  Cum enim eis occurrunt aliquae sophisticae rationes, ex quibus videantur sequi praedictae positiones, et eas nesciunt solvere, concedunt conclusionem.  Unde eorum ignorantia est facile curabilis.  Non enim obviandum est eis vel occurrendum ad rationes quas ponunt, sed ad mentem, ut scilicet solvatur dubitatio de mentibus, per quam in huiusmodi opinions inciderunt.  Et tunc ab istis positionibus recedunt.

“Alii vero praedictas positiones prosequuntur non protper aliquam dubitatoinem eos ad hiuismodi inducentm, sed solum causa orationis, idest ex quaedam protervia, volentes huiusmodi rationes impossibiles sustinere propter seipsa, quia contraria earum demonstrari non possunt.  Et horum medela est argumentatio vel arguitio quae est in voce orationis et in nominibus, idest per hoc quod ipsa vox orationis aliquid significat.  Significatio autem orationis a significatione nomun dependet.  Et sic oportet ad hoc principium redire, quod nomina aliquid significant”.

The Thomistic Concept of Truth

The Lyceum Institute will be co-hosting an inaugural X.com (formerly Twitter) Space, this Thursday (25 April 2024) at 2pm ET, with @Aquinas_Quotes. We will be discussing the Thomistic Concept of Truth. Anyone with an account can listen in! Link below. To facilitate our discussion, we will be considering Thomas Aquinas’ Summa contra Gentiles, 1.61 and De veritate, q.1, a.1, as well as an excerpt from Josef Pieper.

Here is a PDF of the two texts from St. Thomas. Texts from Pieper are attached below.

Science and Philosophy: In Dialogue?

Positivism and Science

A difficult and complex question in philosophy today concerns the discussion regarding the intersection and “boundaries” of the harder empirical sciences and the distinct activity of philosophical enquiry.  Given the success of scientific discovery, one temptation in the early 20th century was to claim that disciplines such as biology, chemistry, physics, and the like were (or would eventually become) exhaustive for understanding the world and nature.  This position, known as “positivism”, claimed that genuine inquiry into the world of nature either had to be reducible to empirical testing and measuring or was known to be true tautologically.[1]  Anything that did not conform to these modes of inquiry, such as classical metaphysics and theology, were considered pseudo-scientific in their mode of enquiry.  

Standing in contrast to this reductive position, the French Thomist philosopher Jacques Maritain argues in his Degrees of Knowledge that a bifurcation can be made between sciences as affirmative, to which he ascribes the empirical “hard” sciences and studies, and the more deductive science of proper “explication” or knowledge of and from first principles:[2]

Briefly, we can say that science in general deals with the necessities immanent in natures, with the universal essences realized in individuals in the concrete and sensible world.  The distinction has been drawn between the explicatory or deductive sciences, which attain to these natures by discovery (constructively in mathematics, and from without to what is within in the case of philosophy), and the affirmative or inductive sciences, which only attain these natures as signs and substitutes, blindly so to say.  These latter have assuredly a certain explicative value, without which they would not be sciences, but which consists in indicating the necessities of things by way of sensible experiment, not by assigning their intelligible reasons.

Maritain’s distinction between the two sciences of the “explicatory” and the “affirmative” does not distinguish entities as they exist in the world, but rather between different ways of grasping entities in the world.  It is this distinction that forms the basis of Maritain’s own investigation and his defense against positivism: namely, the three degrees of abstraction (by which we attain the natures of physical objects, mathematical objects, and metaphysical objects).  Even so, if all Maritain has done here is provide room for a study of metaphysics or a natural philosophy based upon principles, there remains the question as to how the two modes of enquiry interact with one another—if at all.  Are the affirmative sciences corrective of the explicatory?  Do the explicatory sciences have their own interpretive autonomy in relation to what can be measured and analyzed empirically?

The Cenoscopic and Idioscopic

Another distinction made in philosophy, taken first from Jeremy Bentham, but developed by C. S. Peirce is the distinction between cenoscopic and idioscopic sciences. The cenoscopic sciences are characterized by their study of what is common among the many and divergent, and the idioscopic is characterized by the specializing or the breaking apart of inquiry:[3]

In cenoscopy, things escape the eye not by being hidden by virtue of their tininess or hugeness, or their extension over eons of time or involvement in hyper-complexities of culture, but simply by their commonness. Their very obviousness requires a conscious direction of our attention, like that needed to notice the ticking of a clock that your ears were hearing all the while you conversed with someone, but which remained unperceived because you were otherwise occupied…The “idioscopic,” by contrast, is a “look” that is idios – “singular, special(ized)” – and that began to be cultivated in earnest only in modern times. It has become the very glory of modern science, and has brought countless blessings and maledictions into our contemporary biosphere.

Whereas cenoscopy offers us a “grand theory of everything” and seeks to unite the divergent modes of enquiry, idioscopic enquiry by its nature seeks to break apart, to isolate, to experiment upon, and to measure.  Neither science is necessarily wrongheaded in what it seeks to inquire, but both are deficient with regards to understanding the world and how we relate to it:[4]

In summary, these four areas of human knowing – the astronomically big and the microscopically small, the biologically compounded and the culturally complex – invite idioscopic science to don its instruments, mount its experiments, measure and hypothesize about the objects in question, and finally to fashion technologies that will hopefully more deeply integrate humankind with its environment, solve problems and cure diseases.  Still, the great ideal at the heart of all knowledge, namely, the desire to unify data and bring synthesis to multiplicity, floats temptingly over these four areas as it does over the divisions within each of them.  Knowledge by definition tends toward unity.

What philosophy offers the idioscopic (here I’m grafting roughly onto Maritain’s affirmative as roughly equivalent) is a unified whole of the diversity in the hard sciences.  While idioscopic science by its nature compartmentalizes and divides the study of the world, rightfully so within its respective subject-matter, it is at a loss in attempting to find unity within the multitude.  By contrast, the cenoscopic, in providing its own accounts and studies of the world based upon shared commonness, oftentimes misses the mark in its enquiry—one could think of the Eleatic philosophers and their cenoscopic inquiry concluding the impossibility of change and mutation and the eternal permanence to being.

A Habit Formed

Famously in the Nicomachean Ethics, Aristotle quipped that among the commonly identified virtutes, many of them go unnamed.  A virtue famously for Aristotle is taken to be a mean between two vicious extremes, being informed by the goods sought after deficiently or in excess in both vices:[5]

So, virtue, is a purposive disposition, lying in a mean that is relative to us and determined by a rational principle, and by that which a prudent man would use to determine it.  It is a mean between two kinds of vices, one of excess and the other of deficiency; and also, for this reason, that whereas these vices fall short of or exceeding the right measure in both feelings and actions, virtue discovers the mean and chooses it.

The question I would like to ask is: what sort of “unnamed” virtue must a person be formed in today if both the cenoscopic and ideoscopic sciences are to be retained?  Is it healthy to siphon off one habit of cognizing the world in the absence of the other?  Are there points where both scientific inquiries intersect, or one ought to claim priority, and if so, is there a habit needed to secure this intersection?  If there can be found such a habit, what kind of vicious extremes could be seen to impede the exercise of such a virtuous inquiry?

Join the Conversation!

We’ll be discussing these and more conversations in our Philosophical Happy Hour this Wednesday (17 April 2024) and we’d love for you to join. Use the links below!

Philosophical Happy Hour

« »

Come join us for drinks (adult or otherwise) and a meaningful conversation. Open to the public! Held every Wednesday from 5:45–7:15pm ET.


[1] Creath 2022: “Logical Empiricism”, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2023 Edition), Edward N. Zalta & Uri Nodelman (eds.).

[2] Maritain 1937: Distinguer pour unir ou Les degrés du savoir. Reference to the English translation by Bernard Wall, Degrees of Knowledge, 43

[3] Paine 2021: “On the Cenoscopic and Idioscopic and Why They Matter”, in Reality: a journal for philosophical discourse, online [PDF]: 5-6.

[4] Ibid, 12.

[5] c.335/34bc: Ἠθικὰ nικοάχεια in the English translation by J. Thomson, The Nicomachean Ethics, 42.

Obeying Unjust Laws

St. Thomas defines law in Summa Theologiae I-II q. 90 aa. 1-4. It is an ordinance of reason for the sake of the common good made by someone bestowed with the care of the common good and promulgated. Hence, human law, which St. Thomas treats in I-II q. 95, must share the above definition in addition to being derived from the natural law. The corpus of article two brings us to our topic:

As Augustine says in De Libero Arbitrio 1, “A law that is not just does not seem to be a law at all.”  Hence, something has the force of law to the extent that it shares in justice. Now in human affairs something is called just by virtue of its being right (rectum) according to the rule of reason.  But as is clear from what was said above (q. 91, a. 2), the first rule of reason is the law of nature.  Hence, every humanly made law has the character of law to the extent that it stems from the law of nature.  On the other hand, if a humanly made law conflicts with the natural law, then it is no longer a law, but a corruption of law.

Summa theologiae, Ia-IIae, q.95, a.2, c.

In brief, any law that is unjust or is at odds with the natural law is a corruption or perversion of law. We might then ask whether and to what extent do “laws” of this kind indict the legitimacy of the ruler(s) who wrote them and then whether and to what extent the people must oppose and disobey them. We have some guidance from ST I-II q. 96 a. 4:

On the other hand, there are two ways in which laws are unjust. First, in counterpoint to what was said above, they are unjust when they are contrary to the human good either (a) because of their end, as when the lawmaker imposes burdens on his subjects that contribute not to the common welfare but to his own greed or glory, or (b) because of their author, as when someone makes laws that go beyond the authority entrusted to him, or (c) because of their form, as when burdens are distributed unequally over the multitude, even if those burdens are ordered toward the common good.  Laws of this sort are outrages (violentiae) rather than laws, since, as Augustine puts it in De Libero Arbitrio, “What is not just does not seem to be a law.”  Hence, laws of this sort do not bind in conscience (non obligant in foro conscientiae)—except perhaps for the sake of preventing scandal or social unrest (turbatio), in which case a man should cede his right, in accord with Matthew 5:40-41 (“If someone forces you to go one mile, go with him another two …… and if someone takes away your coat, give him your cloak as well”). The second way in which laws can be unjust is by being contrary to the divine good, as are tyrannical laws that induce men to idolatry or to doing anything else that is contrary to divine law.  It is not permissible to obey such laws in any way at all, since as Acts 5:29 says, “We must obey God rather than men.”

Summa theologiae, Ia-IIae, q.96, a.4, c.

There do appear to be instances that one ought not to resist an unjust law to avoid ‘scandal’ or ‘social unrest’ even though the law is an outrage against the human good. However, if the authority does something contrary to divine law, it must not be obeyed at all neither outwardly or inwardly.

Discussion Questions

  1. Is St Thomas consistent in saying there are some outrageous laws that it might be better to permit, but outrageous laws against the divine good ought never be permitted? For instance, if the state passes a law that steals from its citizens, is that not against divine law (sc., the Ten Commandments)? Furthermore, is it not a consequentialist argument that we ought to go along with x, y, or z evil to avoid a worse evil?
  2. St Thomas does seem to be treading lightly here with his “except perhaps” clause. Matthew 5:40-1 concerns, perhaps, private rather than public virtue. If we take the ‘maybe’ here as a ‘no’ and these outrages are not morally binding—which is essentially what the entire article claims—what exactly are we supposed to do?   

Philosophical Happy Hour

« »

Come join us for drinks (adult or otherwise) and a meaningful conversation. Open to the public! Held every Wednesday from 5:45–7:15pm ET.

2024 Spring: Metaphysics – Discovery of Ens inquantum Ens

“Do we in our time have an answer to the question of what we really mean by the world ‘being’? Not at all. So it is fitting that we should raise anew the question of the meaning of Being.” With these words, published in 1927, Martin Heidegger reignited a question—tamped down by modern thought for the previous few centuries—that had dominated most of the previous two millennia. Since the provocative words of Being and Time first hit bookshelves, countless authors have taken up the question again, including many within the Aristotelian-Thomistic tradition. It was, after all, Aristotle who initiated the inquiry in the first place, and Scholasticism had much to contribute: most notably in its most-famous figure, Thomas Aquinas.

But, despite the frequency with which the question again was asked, misunderstandings have continued, as ever, to cloud our vision—just the sort of misunderstandings that left Kant frustrated at the apparent “lack of progress” in metaphysics and propose his constrained “epistemological” system as defining the bounds of inquiry.

Yet, the prevalence of misunderstandings in so abstruse a question as “what is being?” should not prevent us from continuing to inquire. It belongs to us to seek such knowledge, as intimated by the opening line of Aristotle’s Metaphysics, insofar as we are human. We may never answer the question with the kind of narrow certitude one obtains in mathematics. That we obtain such certainties, after all, follows form the narrowness of the inquiry. No object proves as broad and impossible to encompass as being. Nevertheless, Thomist and Aristotelian alike hold that we may discover its meaning truly, if incompletely. In this seminar, we will take up the Aristotelian-Thomistic tradition of inquiry into ens inquantum ens, and begin our entrance into the study of metaphysics. To undertake such a study will require a calm and disciplined mind.

…it is desirable for each thing to be united to its principle; for through this unity consists the perfection of anything whatsoever. For this reason as well is circular motion the most perfect, as Aristotle proves in book VIII of the Physics, for it conjoins the end to the principle. Now, the separate substances—which are the principles of the human intellect, and to which the human intellect is related from itself as the imperfect to the perfect—are not conjoined to the human being except through the intellect: and it is for this reason, too, that the ultimate felicity of the human being consists in this union. Therefore, the human naturally desires knowledge.

Nor is it a valid objection to this that some human beings do not pursue the study of this science: for often are those who desire some end held back from pursuing it by some cause: either on account of the difficulty of seeing the quest through to its conclusion or on account of other occupations. Thus although all human beings desire this knowledge, nevertheless not all can devote themselves to the pursuit of its study, because they are detained by other things: whether by pleasures, or the necessities of the present life, or even because they avoid the labor of learning out of laziness…

…[but] a natural desire does not exist in vain.

Thomas Aquinas 1270/71: Super Sententiam Metaphysicae, lib.1, lec.1, n.4.

The primary texts for this seminar are all available online for free (PDFs will be provided of both primary and supplemental readings) but it is recommended that one have physical copies of both Aristotle’s Metaphysics and Aquinas’ Commentary on Metaphysics. This latter is available in 2 volumes, including Greek, Latin, and English texts of Aristotle’s work, from the Aquinas Institute through the St. Paul Center for Biblical Theology [Volume I] [Volume II]. These large but handsome and sturdy volumes prove beneficial to a contemplative study of the works they contain (and the multi-language-facing layout allows for scholarly precision). The seminar will be conducted remotely through Microsoft Teams. Learn more about our seminars here. Discussions will be held each Saturday. Early access to the platform begins on 16 March 2024. Deadline to register is 4 April 2024. Download the Syllabus for more details.

Registration is Closed

Pricing Comparison

Standard priceBasic Lyceum
Enrollment
Advanced Lyceum EnrollmentPremium Lyceum Enrollment
Benefactor$200 per seminar$903 seminars included
$90 after
8 seminars included
$90 after
Patron$135 per seminar$653 seminars included
$65 after
8 seminars included
$65 after
Participant$60 per seminar$403 seminars included
$40 after
8 seminars included
$40 after

Tradition and Technology

Our extended senses, tools, technologies, through the ages, have been closed systems incapable of interplay or collective awareness.  Now, in the electric age, the very instantaneous nature of co-existence among our technological instruments has created a crisis quite new in human history.  Our extended faculties and senses now constitute a single field of experience which demands that they become collectively conscious.  Our technologies, like our private senses, now demand an interplay and ratio that makes rational co-existence possible.  As long as our technologies were as slow as the wheel or the alphabet or money, the fact that they were separated, closed systems was socially and psychically supportable.  This is not true now when sight and sound and movement are simultaneous and global in extent.  A ratio of interplay among these extensions of our human functions is now as necessary collectively as it has always been for our private and personal rationality in terms of our private senses or “wits,” as they were once called.

Marshall McLuhan 1962: The Gutenberg Galaxy, 6.

To say that we live in unusual times would be an understatement.  Certainly, every age has its own unprecedented happenings, many of which are precipitated by technological advances.  But in the present iteration of the electronic age—that which we can fairly call “digital”—it appears that technological advance and use no longer occurs as separate from the lives of human beings.  In truth, they have never occurred with such separation.  But today, technologies’ essential function, namely the extension of our natural faculties, has in a way exceeded the proportions set by nature.  This technological disproportion presents an unprecedented challenge.

The rapid unfolding of this unprecedented disproportion, as apprehended (but not understood) in the Western-cultural world, has led to many abandoning their intellectual traditions.  This abandonment comes with hope or desperation for new solutions to the problems (such as endemic tendencies towards psychosis, generative intelligence simulators [mistakenly named “artificial intelligence”], the rapid fragmentation of opposed political ideologies, and global economic precarity with instantaneous consequences) which now threaten our civilizations.  But this abandonment itself misperceives the persistent root underlying these newly-emergent problems—a root which is not a problem itself, but a difficulty with which we as human beings must struggle: namely, understanding human nature.

For this understanding, we are fools not to turn with repeated humility to the great works of our tradition.

What is Tradition?

This question—“what is tradition?—proves surprisingly difficult to answer beyond providing the most basic definitions and descriptions.  But as a fundament for any good response to the question, it must be stated that tradition universally consists in the “handing down” of beliefs and behaviors to others.  Tradition proves therefore both something communicated and something essential to communication.  Every word read off a page or spoken aloud presupposes a common linguistic tradition, not only of the particular letters, shapes, or sounds by which the meanings are conveyed, but of those meanings as well.

Thus, we build traditions not only by the things we use, but by the thoughts with which we inform those things.  Put in other words, tradition always finds itself infused with symbols: conventionally-appointed signs which convey universal ideas.

Traditional Signs and the “Idea” of a Tradition

Behind this identification of symbols and tradition lies a deep inquiry into semiotics (the study of the action of signs).  We do not need to make this inquiry, however, to observe the truth that tradition and symbols are intimately related.  All we need is a little reflection.

Think, for instance, of long-enduring religious practices.  One might think of the Catholic Mass, whether in Roman or Orthodox rites.  Here, symbols abound—not only in the appointments of a church building (stained-glass windows, statues, altars, tabernacles, and so on), not only in the vestments of priests and servers (cassock, alb, amice, cincture, stole, chasuble), nor even in their particular adornments and imagery, but also in countless actions and words (every noun, verb, adjective, adverb, conjunction, and preposition including some symbolic signification).  Conveyed thereby are not only millennia of gradually-accumulated practices, but a thinking-through of how we ought to behave with regard to the sacred.

Or, as a very common form of traditional symbolism across varied cultures, consider the practice of vestment: a tradition found not only in Catholicism but in, for instance, Zen Buddhism.  Japanese practitioners are, upon entry into their monastic life, garbed with the kesa, reception of which symbolizes receipt of the Buddha’s teaching and worn throughout daily rituals to remind of one’s commitment.  The meaning of the garment is much more than the garment itself, just as a priest’s opening of the antiphon—Introibo ad altare Dei, “I will go in to the altar of God”—signifies much more than an intent to ascend the stairs of the sanctuary.

We might further think of more common cultural practices that also have a clear symbolic meaning: such putting up decorations for holidays (whether retaining spiritual depth or not), giving gifts on birthdays, eating a large and plentiful meal on Thanksgiving (in the United States, at least), even the act of shaking hands with someone—each means more than the act itself.  We decorate for a holiday not only because we like to make our homes more attractive for a time (do we want our homes unattractive the rest of the year?) and we do not decorate however we please to celebrate the holiday, but in a way that is in keeping with the holiday celebrated.  Putting up pumpkins at Christmas would be quite bizarre, regardless of one’s religious beliefs.  So too, a Christmas tree does not belong at a Fourth of July party.  We give gifts on birthdays not because we are rewarding the person celebrated, but because we wish to convey our joy at his or her life, to commemorate another year of being-together and hopes for the year to come.  Consuming a large meal at Thanksgiving does not celebrate gluttony (even if often it may turn out that way), but expresses gratitude for life itself, with food that not only nourishes but delights.  Shaking hands not only greets the other, but expresses an intention towards that other (and principally, we intend to signify a spirit of cooperation—though an aggressive handshake might signify otherwise).

If we think a little more, we will realize that we participate in traditions through their symbols on an almost daily basis: in prayer, in conversation, in reading, in writing, in almost any interaction with any other human being, we will engage in some symbolic signification of something above and beyond the here and now moment.

Intellectual Traditions

Of particular importance for the Lyceum Institute are intellectual traditions.  An intellectual tradition comprises symbolically-conveyed relations of beliefs which have been handed down from earlier thinkers.  To give an example, we can take a word we just used: namely, “belief”.  What do we mean by this word?  To some, it may signify faith or religious / personal conviction.  Here, however, it is being used in the tradition of Charles Sanders Peirce, who defines it (to paraphrase) as “conviction in the truth of a proposition so as to act in accordance with it when the occasion arises”.  I believe that spilling water on myself is a nuisance, and so I act in a manner that attempts to prevent spilling water on myself.  I believe that truth is a good to be shared, and so, when the opportunities present themselves, I attempt to share the truth.  I believe that C.S. Peirce has insightful things to say, so I try to read his works.  Each of these beliefs shapes my action, because my conviction is not only that they are true, but that the truths they convey are good.

The purpose of an intellectual tradition is to hand on the truths which produce convictions that turn into beliefs.  We uphold an intellectual tradition because we find that it reveals the intelligible truths of being and, in the beliefs it fosters, we are motivated to actions that are good.  These intellectual traditions can be scientific, theological, literary, historical, artistic, religious, and anything in-between.  The Shakespearean sonnet, for instance—a specific metrical poetic form—belongs to an intellectual tradition inasmuch as this form itself, not independently of but irreducible to the content, signifies something beyond itself.  Likewise, the practice of modern scientific methodology forms part of an intellectual tradition, inasmuch as it is believed to discover and indicate explanations for observed phenomena.  So too, the religious practices of churches and temples alike all are informed not only by a tradition of practice but also of intellectual understanding and likely of some theological belief—however well or poorly formed that understanding may be.

But that literary, scientific, or theological traditions are formed well—this requires a kind of synoptic, holistic, and fundamental perspective: a perspective which can be formed only through philosophy.

Philosophical Traditions at the Lyceum

Just as with the above disciplines, philosophy, too, both produces and develops within intellectual traditions.  Unlike those mentioned above, however—although a certain exception must be made for theology—philosophy encompasses the whole of human experience, including that which is pursued in all other intellectual pursuits.  Nothing falls outside of its domain.[2]

In light of this truth, perhaps no intellectual traditions have as fundamental an importance for our earthly lives as those of philosophy, for it is within and through philosophy that our beliefs about diverse matters can be resolved into a unity.  As these philosophical resolutions gradually grow—one truth illuminating another, another dissolving a false opinion, and yet another coming from the connections drawn between the truth and falsity, and so on—they form a tradition.  Put otherwise, a philosopher establishes some premise as a principle.  From this premise, further conclusions are drawn.  These relations of premises and conclusions are taught to others, students.  These others discover yet further meanings in light of the earlier thinking.  Often, the teachers and students alike write down their thinking.  Thus, the tradition grows not only from mouth to ear, but from pages through eyes.

As more is written—and as traditions come into conflict with one another—their reception becomes increasingly complex.  If we do not read Plato himself, but only what is said about him by others, we do not truly know Plato’s thought, even if those others are accurate.  Conversely, if we read only Plato himself, we inevitably will miss certain truths about his thinking that others have perceived and explained.  Doubtless we will discover with little enough reading, commentaries upon Plato often conflict with one another.  It belongs to a student of Platonic thinking, then, not merely to receive the tradition’s conclusions but, much more poignantly, to re-think its questions.

Such is the approach to philosophical traditions taken at the Lyceum Institute.  We give certain traditions—Platonism, Aristotelianism, Thomism and Scholasticism generally, Peircean semiotics, certain thinkers within phenomenology and hermeneutics—greater emphasis than others because the questions they ask, and the answers provided to them, have proven better explanations than those given by those others.  Because philosophy asks perennial questions, and because its answers are not like the solutions to simple mathematical equations, one cannot simply appropriate a tradition; one must live within it.  Doing so develops a philosophical habit, and it is through this habit that we are able to face new challenges and difficulties.

What is Technology?

Among the emphasized philosophical traditions mentioned above, one will find commonly a tendency towards what can call realism: that is, simply put, the belief that our knowledge, at least in part, really is of things as they are in themselves.  Many other philosophical traditions are not realist, in at least some one or another important way.  Whether one is a realist or an anti-realist will change how one understands technology: for the latter, since human nature itself remains essentially unintelligible, technology can only be a construct of our own making.  For the former, the realist, technology can instead be understood as an extension of human faculties.

Asking the Right Questions

This notion—that technology extends our faculties—requires, of course, that we understand what those faculties are and how they function.  The author quoted at the outset of this article, Marshall McLuhan, dedicated much of his career to discovering the relations between diverse kinds and instruments of technology and the human sense faculties.  His seminal 1964 book, Understanding Media: the Extensions of Man, considers (among many others) as such technologies: spoken and written words, clothing, money, printing, photographs, automobiles, games, movies, radio, television, and automation.  As each use of one technology increases, McLuhan argues, the ratio of our senses is changed.  Some pull us into more of a visual modality; others, auditory; others still, the tactile.

Through the alteration of these ratios, we alter also the environments of our human and especially social living.  We human beings have been shifting the ratio of our senses since before recorded history.  Indeed, such shifts were required to invent the means of recording: the development of languages and the means of their preservation as an extension of memory.  But while we can conceive easily enough certain superficial extensions of our faculties—writing an extension of memory, photographs an extension of sight (allowing us to see things from the past)—the complex interplay of these technological extensions often eludes our awareness. 

Allow me to suggest that this elusiveness belongs not to the technological devices or products, but rather to the fact that technologies never exist independently of human beings.  That is, technologies come into being through human invention, yes; but more importantly, they operate as technologies only in relation to some human purpose.  Automate a technology to continue past all human existence, and it may continue to function.  But will it continue to function as a technology?

In other words: what makes a technology to be a technology?  What do we really mean when we say the word, “technology”?  Of course this question is not new.  But do we have (have we ever had?) the right intellectual traditions to answer it?  Can we incorporate such answers into a philosophical tradition?

Technology and Human Environments

As we have already mentioned, technological innovation and use alters—we may even say, to some degree, constitutes—the environments of human experience.  Connections between the advent of automobiles and the development of suburbs, for instance, are well known.  To many, this exodus from the urban life of city and town has a double concern: first, the evacuation of the cities themselves.  As McLuhan writes in Understanding Media, “There is a growing uneasiness about the degree to which cars have become the real population of our cities, with a resulting loss of human scale, both in power and in distance.”[3]  As anyone who has lived in or near a city or sizable town can likely attest, the car presents a struggle: it requires much real estate for driving and for parking—increasing both horizontally and vertically the expanse of concrete, pushing out shops, stores, restaurants; destroying neighborhoods and communities alike.

But secondly, the remove of persons to suburban environments likewise has an effect on our psychology, as well.  It makes us much more private.  Our suburban neighbors are always there—but merely there.  We may work in entirely different directions; we may commute long distances; we may shop at different stores; our kids may go to different schools; we may have naught in common as to the conduct of daily life but for the fact that we live on the same street.  The destruction of human scale inhibits our formation of communities; and the lack of communities affects the mind of each human being who needs such community in order to thrive.

The impact of technological developments upon our lives, in other words, consists not only in a physical reshaping of the environment, but also the psychological restructuring, which always plays a role in environmental constitution.  How we look at things—how we think about them—has a way of changing how they fit into our lives.  But if technology changes how we look at and think about things, how we hear what they have to say, then clearly it is also important that we perceive and think correctly about technology, as well.

Digital Paradigm of Technology

In the past several decades, a new paradigm of technology has become increasingly prevalent in this, the electric age: namely, the digital.  Few have sufficiently considered the weight of this shift.  While the first several decades of electricity saw communication transferred primarily through analog means—where one medium is used to represent one or another, but with a physical limitation that constrained the suitability of instruments (e.g., you could not produce a photograph on a vinyl record, or record sound in a Polaroid)—the increasing translation of records into digital formats has radically altered the human environment of today.

Where previous technological innovations have altered the ratios of our faculties, that is, the digital has altered it beyond all proportionality.  It homogenizes all data: images, sounds, representations of tactility, relations and patterns of relationships.  It captures with deceitfully-perfect seeming-fidelity not only the real, but so too the fake; fact and fiction become, in a digital paradigm of preservation and re-presentation, increasingly indistinguishable.  We may witness this through the big-budget cinematic film, in which the digital creation of imagery and sound has become increasingly difficult to distinguish, as to what belongs really to things themselves and what was created through some other means.[4]  As we blur lines between reality and fantasy, we damage the faculties of perceptual distinction upon which we intellectually rely.  Reciprocally, the less we strive to develop our intellectual habits, the more damaging these sensory distortions become.

As the digital permeates our environments ever deeper—integrating into our homes, our devices, our communications, ever-present through one or another screen, always ready-to-hand through the phones in our pockets—we urgently need to ask: how do we understand these technologies?  How do they fit coherently into human life?

Philosophical Tradition and Technology

Many propose responding to this question with the Luddite answer: eliminate the technology, either in itself or from your life; disconnect your homes and your devices, sign off of your accounts, live in a technologically-minimalist way.  Doubtless, this answer appeals to many.  Modern life causes no shortage of exhaustion and a retreat from its technological instruments promises a desirable rest.  But though this may prove a solution to the problem of one’s own individual living, it does nothing to resolve the essential and essentially-human difficulty of technology.  Fleeing from technology will not give us understanding of it, and thus—sooner or later, in our lives or those of generations yet to come—technology will grow again.

Instead, to handle the difficulty, we need philosophy.  But what we need more than merely a set of philosophical doctrines.  We need a philosophical tradition that instills in us a habit of careful thinking about the phenomena that not only surround us, but that shape and constitute the environment in which we live.

Thoughtful Engagement of the Digital Paradigm

Most especially do we need this habit of thoughtful reflection within the digital paradigm.  As mentioned above, the weaker our habits of thinking, the more damaging we may find this most-pervasive of technological developments.  Most readers of this essay, it is expected, are wary of social media: its effects on the psychological well-being of youth have become a hot topic no less than the proliferation of “fake news”.  But it influences us in more subtle ways, as well, providing us not only with unhealthy self-images or untrue claims, but also changing our very patterns of thinking.

It may seem silly, perhaps, to look for answers about how we ought to live in the digital age from thinkers who died centuries ago, thinkers who never experienced technologies or modes of life quite like our own—thinkers like Aristotle and Aquinas.  But although the particulars of our own day differ from these thinkers of antiquity, their insights into the universal truths of the human being remain ever-pertinent, and, if we can engage these traditions thoughtfully, we will find ways to bring their insights into an illuminating dialogue with the unique particulars of our own day.

The first task for a philosophical tradition appointed to initiating such a dialogue is the articulation of technology’s essence.  The Lyceum Institute is taking up this task in a year-long project, Humanitas Technica, which will run throughout 2024, including an extended and expansive seminar to take place in the Fall.  We have already begun preliminary conversations—covering how our relationship with technology has gone wrong, the conception of technology held by those responsible for creating it, and begun a preliminary consideration of technology’s definition.  These preliminary conversations serve to illuminate the questions still to be asked.  But primarily, they have shown that most of our technologies—even those that seemingly concern naught but the change of physical entities—modify our relations of communication.

Questioning Presuppositions

This centrality of communication to all technologies brings to light two common presuppositions: first, that technologies are principally instruments; and second, that they are inherently neutral in themselves and only incidentally used for good or evil.  Recasting the conversation about technology—such that we consider technological instruments not principally through what they do according to their own forms but what we do through them in our most human capacities, and how this activity reverberates into us—challenges both these presuppositions.

To unfold this claim for recasting the conversation requires both the strength of a philosophical anthropology, such as that found in the Aristotelian-Thomistic tradition, and the robust understanding of signification found both in late developments of Latin Thomistic thinkers and the semiotics of Charles Sanders Peirce.  These latter considerations—concerning signs, symbols, and their interpretation—will allow us not only to apply our traditions to the technological developments of recent decades or those to come in the future, but to fold technology itself into these traditions.  What is a smartphone?  A piece of protective equipment?  A new medicine?  To understand such innovations, we cannot ask only what they do, but how we understand them.  For this, semiotics will prove essential.

Many other contributions across diverse philosophical traditions of realism, no doubt, will find their place in these conversations as well.  But regardless of the insights’ sources, it is a conversation which needs to be had and one which indeed requires recasting.  The growing cultural problems—worry over which fills our publications, our daily discussions, the anxieties which gnaw at the souls of parents and teachers alike—all appear exacerbated by the technological environment we now inhabit.

Traditions of Philosophical Realism and Technology

Much more remains to be said on this topic, and I have little doubt that the many fine people involved in Humanitas Technica will have much worthwhile to say, but allow one final point here.

If we cannot know things as they are independently of our minds—know them not only according to their sense-perceptual, empirically-observable, mathematically-calculable attributes but according to their intelligible and universal essences—then technology may have all the effects mentioned above, but we cannot know or discern their causality.  From any anti-realist perspective, our concern with technology cannot but become one that is merely instrumental, and, ultimately, which aims at using technology for dominance.

By contrast, the traditions of realist philosophy, which not only possess the capacity to unveil technology’s essence but also to discover its possible coherences and incoherencies with human nature, enables us to use technology well.  This good use can come only through inculcating the philosophical habit.  Such a habit, which enables us not only to handle the digital paradigm but to navigate future difficulties as well, comes not through a set curriculum of courses, nor through receiving the right information, nor even through studying the right figures, but from continuing to question.


[2] So too, theology: but the subject matter of theology, properly speaking—at least according to the Catholic intellectual tradition—is provided by divine revelation; and thus, to enter into its study properly, one must possess a certain faith, for all things as they fall under the umbrella of theological study resolve not to human experience, but to the divine eschaton.

[3] 1964: Understanding Media, 293.

[4] In truth, the sound of films has almost always been created by something other than what is represented through the screen—the industry having relied for long upon what is termed Foley art to make sounds more convincing than those that can be captured by on-set microphones.

2024 Winter: Good and Freedom in Aquinas’ De Veritate

Why do we call a thing “good”?  We have been calling things good since childhood, but, as with any conception so fundamental, it is challenging to unfold its meaning.  Given the multifarious use of this name, “good”, is there even a unity of meaning to discover?  Is it just that we call anything good merely because it occasions feelings of a certain kind, or is there something in things themselves that justifies calling them good? 

Thomas Aquinas proposes that, indeed, the conception of the good has a central meaning –  “that which is perfective in the manner of a final cause” – and so approves the dictum of Aristotle, that “the good is that which all seek”.

Affectivity is thus relevant to this central meaning of the good, but affectivity understood, in those beings that have it, as essentially correlated with real possibilities, with the relationship of a thing to that which would perfect or fulfill it.  This is the order to an end, or final cause – a challenge to a reductive modern paradigm in which reality contains no real possibilities, but only “actual facts” of a mechanical kind. 

In this seminar, we will follow Aquinas’s treatment of the good in questions 21-26 of his great work known as De veritate.  Our considerations will include the metaphysics of the good, the divine will, and the human faculties that engage with the good, namely human will and the capacity for free choice, and human sensuality.  We will also touch on the connections between some important passages in De veritate and the topic of evil. 

Therefore, among these three things that Augustine affirms, the last one, namely order, is the relation which the name of goodness implies. But the other two, that is species and mode, cause that relation. For species pertains to the very notion of the species which, inasmuch as it has being in another, is received in some determinate mode, since whatever exists in another exists within it in the manner of the receiver. Therefore, every good thing, inasmuch as it is perfective with respect to the notion of species and being, as taken together, has mode, species, and order. It has species with respect to the notion itself of species, it has mode with respect to existence, and order with respect to the condition of what perfects.

Thomas Aquinas i.1256-59: Quaestiones disputatae de veritate, q.21, a.6, c.

Registration

Lyceum Institute seminar costs are structured on a principle of financial subsidiarity. There are three payment levels, priced according to likely levels of income. If you wish to take a seminar but cannot afford the suggested rate, it is acceptable to sign up at a less-expensive level. The idea is: pay what you can. Those who can pay more, should, so that those who cannot pay as much, need not. Lyceum Institute members receive a further discount (see here for details).

One payment covers all 8 weeks.

If you prefer an alternative payment method (i.e., not PayPal), use our contact form and state whether you prefer to pay as a Participant, Patron, or Benefactor, and an invoice will be emailed to you.

Pricing Comparison

Standard priceBasic Lyceum
Enrollment
Advanced Lyceum EnrollmentPremium Lyceum Enrollment
Benefactor$200 per seminar$903 seminars included
$90 after
8 seminars included
$90 after
Patron$135 per seminar$653 seminars included
$65 after
8 seminars included
$65 after
Participant$60 per seminar$403 seminars included
$40 after
8 seminars included
$40 after

Complete Lyceum Catalog – 2024

We have completed our 2024 catalog and preliminary schedule for all seminars and courses!  While these are, of course, always subject to change (life being ever-unpredictable), I am happy to announce this very exciting slate of philosophy seminars for the upcoming year:

Seminar Catalog 2024

Winter (Q1)

Introduction to Philosophical Thinking

– Brian Kemple

Phenomenology: Heidegger’s Method II

– Brian Kemple

Thinkers: Aquinas’ De Veritate – Good and Freedom

– Kirk Kanzelberger


Summer (Q3)

Culture & Politics: A Thomistic Defense of Democracy

– Francisco Plaza

Science: The Physics of Aristotle

– Daniel Wagner

Spring (Q2)

Philosophers and History

– Scott Randall Paine

Semiotics: an Introduction

– Brian Kemple

Metaphysics: Discovery of Ens inquantum Ens

– Brian Kemple


Fall (Q4)

Science: An Existential Thomistic Noetics – Maritain’s Degrees of Knowledge and Late-Life Works on Epistemology

– Matthew Minerd

Metaphysics: The Doctrine of Analogy

– Brian Kemple

Semiotics: The Difficulties of Technology

– Group seminar (multiple instructors)


Seven of the eleven seminars on our schedule are new, never before offered.  There may also be others added to the Summer schedule, drawing upon our archives (which are undergoing a massive overhaul to be more accessible and useful).  All-in-all, I find myself a bit giddy at the line-up for the year.  You will find descriptions for each seminar in this PDF.

Trivium, Latin, and Greek

We have also previously announced our Trivium, Latin, and Greek schedules. All of the core courses in these studies are available to every enrolled Lyceum Institute member. Sign up today to begin studying with us in January!

Looking forward to another great year of study and we hope you will join us!

On Natural Law and Justice

In his work Introduction to Moral Theology, Fr. Romanus Cessario O.P. remarked on certain misconceptions with respect to how the natural had grown in application and importance over time in the late 19th and early 20th centuries: arguing that the presentation of the natural law given in teaching manuals was anachronistic and unhelpful, and in extreme cases was at times influenced by Suarezian or casuist trends in moral theology.

The casuistry embedded in the Roman Catholic manual tradition greatly contributed to misinterpretations of natural law. Although Prummer follows Aquinas’ own material distinctions, this sort of presentation nonetheless reinforces the misconception that Catholic moral theology is given to consider every specific moral issue as if natural law alone supplied the ultimate determination. The manualist misconstrues of natural law also explain the tendency among some contemporary authors to think that natural law theory supplies the equivalent of a complete moral theory… Natural law is not the only resource needed for a complete theory of Christian morality. A realist moral theologian recognizes that natural law provides a starting point for discovering the concrete forms of moral goodness.[1]

Romanus Cessario, Introduction to Moral Theology

Natural Law and Justice

If a scholar of Aquinas were to look at what the Angelic Doctor wrote on the natural law in the Summa Theologiae, they would be surprised to find very little actually discussed by St. Thomas. Fewer than twenty questions in the Prima Secundæ are devoted to questions specifically concerning law and only one of them to the natural law. By contrast, what Aquinas had to say on the virtues, more specifically the virtue of justice, greatly eclipses what he wrote on law.  Questions 57-122 are all devoted to discussing the importance and concrete application of justice, and the entirety of the Secunda Secundæ discusses the virtues in general.

Aquinas, in discussing the natural law, outlines the precepts of the law in the Summa, arguing that the precepts of natural law are roughly equivalent to first principles in speculative sciences and demonstration. They provide us the starting point, as it were, for praxis and practical reasoning:

[T]he precepts of the natural law are to the practical reason, what the first principles of demonstrations are to the speculative reason; because both are self-evident principles… Since, however, good has the nature of an end, and evil, the nature of a contrary, hence it is that all those things to which man has a natural inclination, are naturally apprehended by reason as being good, and consequently as objects of pursuit, and their contraries as evil, and objects of avoidance. Wherefore according to the order of natural inclinations, is the order of the precepts of the natural law. Because in man there is first of all an inclination to good in accordance with the nature which he has in common with all substances: inasmuch as every substance seeks the preservation of its own being, according to its nature: and by reason of this inclination, whatever is a means of preserving human life, and of warding off its obstacles, belongs to the natural law. Secondly, there is in man an inclination to things that pertain to him more specially, according to that nature which he has in common with other animals: and in virtue of this inclination, those things are said to belong to the natural law, “which nature has taught to all animals” [Pandect. Just. I, tit. i], such as sexual intercourse, education of offspring and so forth. Thirdly, there is in man an inclination to good, according to the nature of his reason, which nature is proper to him: thus, man has a natural inclination to know the truth about God, and to live in society: and in this respect, whatever pertains to this inclination belongs to the natural law; for instance, to shun ignorance, to avoid offending those among whom one has to live, and other such things regarding the above inclination.[2]

In Summa Theologiae Ia-IIae qu. 94 art. 1

A problem one might face with Aquinas’ theory is that the natural law, or more specifically its precepts, do not determine their own application. A sentiment as universal as “striving towards living in a society and avoiding offense against those with whom one has to live” might be admirable, but it can hardly help determine for us the day-to-day demands of justice—especially living in an increasingly technocratic and hyper-communicative world. These principles may indeed be what ought to form the basis of our practical reasoning, but they are not principles which determine their own application. Aquinas is aware that this is the case, and in discussing justice as it pertains to the virtue of epieikeia (reasonable accommodation of circumstances in pursuit of equity), writes how justice is that with which laws are concerned, and principally deal.

When we were treating of laws, since human actions, with which laws are concerned, are composed of contingent singulars and are innumerable in their diversity, it was not possible to lay down rules of law that would apply to every single case. Legislators in framing laws attend to what commonly happens: although if the law be applied to certain cases, it will frustrate the equality of justice and be injurious to the common good, which the law has in view.[3]

In Summa Theologiae IIa-IIae qu. 120 art. 1

Relationality of Justice

Interestingly enough, Aquinas, in treating the virtue of justice, notes how it is more principally the virtue pertaining to the virtuous person as it especially stands in importance among the different virtues. Speaking of the subjective qualities of the soul, it simply is better on account of its residing in reason, but also because it is precisely through justice that we can be good towards other people, rather than being good in ourselves.

If we speak of legal justice, it is evident that it stands foremost among all the moral virtues, for as much as the common good transcends the individual good of one person. On this sense the Philosopher declares (Ethic. v, 1) that “the most excellent of the virtues would seem to be justice, and more glorious than either the evening or the morning star.” But, even if we speak of particular justice, it excels the other moral virtues for two reasons. The first reason may be taken from the subject, because justice is in the more excellent part of the soul, viz. the rational appetite or will, whereas the other moral virtues are in the sensitive appetite, whereunto appertain the passions which are the matter of the other moral virtues. The second reason is taken from the object, because the other virtues are commendable in respect of the sole good of the virtuous person himself, whereas justice is praiseworthy in respect of the virtuous person being well disposed towards another, so that justice is somewhat the good of another person, as stated in Ethic. v, 1. Hence the Philosopher says (Rhet. i, 9): “The greatest virtues must needs be those which are most profitable to other persons, because virtue is a faculty of doing good to others. For this reason, the greatest honors are accorded the brave and the just, since bravery is useful to others in warfare, and justice is useful to others both in warfare and in time of peace.”[4]

In Summa Theologiae IIa-IIae qu. 58 art. 12

Justice then seems to be just as important—if not even more so—than the precepts of the natural law, because it is only through justice that right relations between different members of a given society can obtain. Not only relations with family members, or friends, but lawgivers, employers, statesmen, and the like all require the application of justice.

Understanding Justice in our Contemporary Context

Putting aside justice as conventionally understood by Aquinas in his 13th century medieval context, what would he have to say with regards to the application of social media and communication-based technology that we have encountered and utilized in the 21st century? Is justice something that concerns us insofar as we employ social media? Do we have some sort of obligation towards justice in how we interact with each other socially online? My question then for us all for Wednesday is; what is the relationship between the natural law, or more specifically the precepts of the natural law and the virtue of justice, and what does it mean then to be justice today given the widespread use of social media and technology?

Philosophical Happy Hour

« »

Come join us for drinks (adult or otherwise) and a meaningful conversation. Open to the public! Held every Wednesday from 5:45–7:15pm ET.


[1] Cessario, R. (2001). Introduction to Moral Theology. : Catholic University of America Press. Pg. 104

[2] In Summa Theologiae Ia-IIae qu. 94 art. 1 Second and Revised Edition, 1920, Literally translated by Fathers of the English Dominican Province, Online Edition Copyright © 2017 by Kevin Knight https://www.newadvent.org/summa/2094.htm#article1

[3] In Summa Theologiae IIa-IIae qu. 120 art. 1 https://www.newadvent.org/summa/3120.htm

[4] In Summa Theologiae IIa-IIae qu. 58 art. 12  https://www.newadvent.org/summa/3058.htm#article12